Exploring the idea of science as a social institution is a central theme in several of the provided sources. Science, in this context, is not simply a body of knowledge or a set of methods, but rather a complex web of norms, practices, discourses, and organizational structures endorsed by society to produce what it considers authoritative truths about the world, ourselves, and our societies.
**Defining Science as a Social Institution:**
Science as an institution is characterized by both formal and informal norms that guide shared understandings of what is proper, right, or true. These norms are embedded within a family of institutional practices and discourses. The truths produced by science are often seen as issuing from formalized methods and procedures designed to ensure a degree of objectivity, creating a distance between the inquirer and the object of study, allowing the objects to "speak for themselves". However, what counts as science is not static but varies historically due to its continuous self-revisions.
**Social and Cultural Embeddedness of Science:**
The sources strongly emphasize that science is not conducted in a vacuum but is deeply embedded in social, cultural, economic, and political contexts. Weber argued that in modern rationalized culture, science is accompanied by a specific form of rationality ("means-ends" rationality) and a narrowing of imaginative possibilities. Bourdieu also highlights how the acquisition of knowledge within academic and scientific fields can become a mechanism of social division. He suggests that a scientist is a "scientific field made flesh," with cognitive structures homologous to the field's structure and constantly adjusted to its expectations.
Haraway's concept of "situated knowledges" underscores that all scientific knowledge is produced from particular, limited viewpoints, necessarily from somewhere, rather than from a universal standpoint. Scientific communities become socially responsible when they acknowledge these limitations and speak from their structured locations. Lloyd emphasizes that objectivity in science results from the critical interaction of diverse groups and individuals with different social and cultural assumptions and stakes, making social components an essential part of scientific practice.
**Science and Power:**
Several sources discuss the intricate relationship between science and power. Foucault, for instance, explored the political status of science and its potential ideological functions. He argued that power and knowledge are intertwined, and this interweaving can be more readily grasped in areas of knowledge with a less solid epistemological profile, like psychiatry, which are closely linked to social regulation. Even medicine, with a stronger scientific basis, is profoundly enmeshed in social structures.
Gardiner notes that mainstream social science, with its orientation towards "structures" and "institutions," and its emphasis on narrow, purposive rationality, can be seen as a hegemonic enterprise that seeks to impose itself on competing, non-official knowledges. This is achieved by isolating practices from their everyday context and treating them as "pure facts," formulated as objective principles and subjected to the "sociological gaze". The adoption of "scientific objectivity" can represent an imposition of power, bypassing the éthico-political qualities of social relationships. Bourdieu argues that abstract theoretical reason cannot capture all nuances of everyday practice and can perpetrate "symbolic violence" upon it, bolstering elitism and hyper-specialization.
Mahon highlights the "normalization of society" through the fusion of disciplinary practices, scientific knowledges, and new social structures. The emergence of technological knowledge, for example, involved a struggle between different "knowledges," with the state introducing norms for communication and comparison, leading to a hierarchical classification and centralization of knowledge. This process established "the constraint of science," where claims are judged based on the speaker's or journal's scientific authority.
**Critiques of Scientific Objectivity and Value-Neutrality:**
The notion of science as a purely objective and value-neutral enterprise is challenged by several sources. Weber argued that "scientific truth is only valid for those who seek truth," emphasizing that all knowledge is conditioned by a cultural context and ideas about what is significant. Bourdieu similarly argues against the "illusion of foundation" in theoretical knowledge, which often refuses to "objectify the objectifying subject".
Habermas critiqued positivism for concealing a commitment to a particular form of rationality behind a veil of value-neutrality. He argued that even seemingly objective scientific research is embedded in a lifeworld with its own assumptions and values. Positivism, by failing to reflect on its social conditions of emergence, projects its own values as universal. The selection of problems and the choice of sciences to address them also reflect underlying assumptions and values.
Feyerabend viewed science as just one of the many ideologies that propel society and argued for a formal separation between state and science, similar to the separation between state and church. He believed science should influence society only to the extent that any other political or pressure group is permitted.
**The Role of Social Processes in Scientific Knowledge Production:**
Popper emphasized the "public character of scientific method," highlighting the importance of free criticism within a scientific community. He argued that scientific progress depends on instruction and selection, involving both a conservative element and a revolutionary use of trial and error through criticism and empirical testing. Social interaction is crucial for critical rationalism because individuals are often blind to their own failings.
Beebee argues that the epistemic reliability of scientific practices depends not only on the possibility of true theories but also on the social, economic, political, and cultural factors that ensure approximately true answers are publicized and investigated. The lone, unfunded researcher with a correct conjecture does not contribute to the reliability of scientific practices until their work is taken seriously within the scientific community.
**Alternative Perspectives and Critiques from within Social Theory:**
The sources highlight different approaches within social theory to understanding science. The "third-person perspective" (objectivist) camp in social theory attempts to isolate observable and quantifiable "social facts," exemplified by Durkheim's analysis of suicide. In contrast, the "first-person perspective" (hermeneutic) camp focuses on understanding the beliefs and opinions of everyday social actors through principles of interpretation.
Postmodernist attempts to understand science in terms of social construction have also gained traction. This perspective focuses on scientists as rational agents whose reflection is influenced and conditioned by sociological and biological frameworks.
Critical theorists like Horkheimer and Adorno, drawing on Weber, argued that the growth of scientific rationality represents a growing means of domination. The sociology of scientific knowledge (SSK) further challenged positivistic philosophies of science by emphasizing the social and historical contexts of scientific discovery and insisting on sociological explanations for all scientific beliefs.
**Science and the "Lifeworld":**
Habermas's concept of the "lifeworld" is relevant here. He argues that as science becomes increasingly specialized, it splits off from the lifeworld, leading to laypeople losing the capacity to integrate cognitive, normative, and aesthetic understandings of reality in a critical way. However, he also acknowledges that scientific discourses do permeate lay culture, playing a role in maintaining social stability by generating consensus. Philosophy, according to Habermas, can act as an interpreter between science and the lifeworld, refurbishing the link between specialized knowledge and the totality of lived experience.
**Conclusion:**
The idea of science as a social institution reveals its multifaceted nature, extending beyond mere objective inquiry. It is shaped by social norms, values, power dynamics, historical contexts, and cultural influences. Understanding science in this way allows for a more critical and nuanced perspective on its authority, its role in society, and its relationship with other forms of knowledge and social practices. The sources emphasize the need for reflexivity, acknowledging the situatedness of scientific knowledge and the interplay between science and the broader social world.