**Getting Started: The Author's Take on Galileo**
Stillman Drake, the author, makes it clear from the get-go that he's not just rehashing the usual tales. His primary focus in this "short" introduction is the deeply significant event of Galileo's condemnation by the Roman Inquisition in 1633. He uses Galileo's entire biography as the backdrop to understand this turning point in cultural history.
Drake argues that the common assumption of an inevitable conflict between science and religion, often illustrated by Galileo's case, is a cliché that originated largely _from_ this very case, rather than being its cause. He suggests a simpler explanation might lie in the general tendency of societal authority to suppress minority opinion, with Aristotelianism being the dominant authority Galileo clashed with, rather than Christianity itself.
Now, here's where Drake offers a potentially surprising hypothesis that runs contrary to widely held beliefs: he posits that Galileo was a zealot, not for the Copernican astronomy itself, but for the future health of the Catholic Church and for protecting religious faith from any scientific discovery that might come along. He argues this idea can resolve many long-standing historical puzzles surrounding the Galileo affair. This might seem "highly improbable" at first glance, but Drake encourages us to explore it as a potential lens.
Drake portrays Galileo not as an unreasoning Copernican zealot battling tradition from a young age, but as a prudent man, careful with evidence, aware of social norms, and generally disinclined to pick fights with powerful figures. Most of his controversies were sparked by others attacking his work. The author even suggests Galileo's frequent expressions of zeal for the Church, often dismissed as mere convention by historians, might have been deeply sincere, perhaps even motivating the risks he took which ultimately led to punishment.
Drake emphasizes that judging Galileo's personality independently, rather than deducing it from his conflict with the Inquisition, is key to understanding the events. He sees Galileo as a human being capable of independent thought and decision, not just a "puppet" of intellectual forces. He points to Galileo's trusted relationships with universities and grand dukes as evidence that responsible people didn't see him as a troublemaker, even though he was known to be a "pugnacious fighter" for causes he believed just.
**Galileo's Approach to Science: A Breath of Fresh Air?**
Let's talk about what Galileo was actually _doing_ in science, because it was quite different from the norm of his day. The standard approach, especially in universities, was Aristotelian natural philosophy. This sought to understand the _causes_ and ultimate _purpose_ of things through reasoning and logical rules, not by measuring. Aristotle's system was based on four elements, four qualities, and ideas of natural places and tendencies. It was a complete, closed system of conclusions about physics and astronomy.
Galileo, however, began to forge a different path. His physics was founded on his _own actual measurements_, leading him to discover laws like the law of falling bodies. This wasn't a medieval approach, nor was it purely philosophical, as philosophy focused on causes, not laws found through measurement. Galileo famously asked, "What has philosophy... got to do with measuring anything?".
For Galileo, mathematics wasn't just an abstract exercise; it was the essential "language" needed to "read" the "great book of nature". His science wasn't a closed system of final conclusions; it was a _method_, expected to remain piecemeal and incomplete. He rejected the idea of ever completely understanding even the "least effect in Nature," seeing such "vain presumption" as based on "never understanding anything".
He explicitly saw his approach as a rival to Aristotelian natural philosophy. He didn't rely on medieval concepts like "mean-speed" analysis or "impetus" in his key work on falling bodies. His mathematical concepts and procedures were distinct from medieval natural philosophers. While he adopted some terminology from enlightened Aristotelianism at Padua, his method, involving careful measurement and mathematical proportionality, was opposed by leading Aristotelians like Cesare Cremonini. Drake notes it's easy to try and link Galileo to various philosophical systems because his writings contain elements many philosophies could draw upon, but he didn't ground his science in any one.
Galileo suggested that ordinary, intelligent people with their "eyes in their head and with their wits about them" could understand nature's works without philosophical guides. He saw scientists as the "less worthy artificers" who extract the "marble" (raw findings) from which sculptors (philosophers) might later create "marvellous figures". This view implied that science, pursued through demonstration and reasoning accessible to humans, wouldn't necessarily answer all questions, even many of interest.
Initially, Galileo did attempt to investigate motion using causal reasoning learned at university. However, he later explicitly set aside the investigation of causes, calling such philosophical debates "fantasies" that offered "little gain". His new basis was "careful measurement," replacing the search for causes with the search for "physical laws". He saw observation and experiment as the "solid foundation of science," providing the "only certainty" he attributed to his conclusions.
He restricted science to things that could be established on "sensory experiences and necessary demonstrations". This contrasts with later physics like Newton's universal inertial law, which Galileo was cautious about extending universally, preferring to leave such speculation to philosophers. For Galileo, science was concerned with the properties of things and observed events, not the "essences" of things, marking a declaration of independence from philosophy. He aimed to distinguish different kinds of things (like sensations from external phenomena) that philosophers often confused.
In essence, Galileo wasn't just offering new conclusions; he was proposing a fundamentally different _way_ of doing science, grounded in measurement, mathematics, and observation, separate from the philosophical quest for ultimate causes and complete understanding.
**Early Conflicts and Discoveries: Finding His Way**
Galileo's early career shows a fascinating evolution. While teaching at Pisa, his first lengthy manuscript followed the standard, conventional style of natural philosophy, showing "hardly any trace of originality" and even rejecting Copernicanism. However, he soon began questioning Aristotle's conclusions and attacked his physics in his Pisan treatise _De motu_.
Though the famous story of him dropping weights from the Leaning Tower of Pisa might be more legend than fact (first told by a protégé born after Galileo's death), it likely reflects real arguments he had with philosophy professors who taught Aristotle's rules of fall. Galileo probably used such demonstrations, perhaps privately or for students, to challenge the established views. He was cautious about publishing, withholding _De motu_ because its conclusions didn't fully match experiments, a trait he later described as preferring accuracy over rushing to print.
His move from the poorly paid position at Pisa to the more distinguished one at the tolerant University of Padua, under Venetian rule, marked a positive step. At Padua, he interacted with influential figures like G.V. Pinelli, Fra Paolo Sarpi, and Robert Cardinal Bellarmine. Sarpi, the Venetian theologian known for his conflict with Rome, became a close friend to whom Galileo first revealed his law of fall and telescope observations. Cardinal Bellarmine, a key figure in later events, also respected Galileo, which Drake sees as significant.
Galileo's interest in Copernicanism seems to have solidified around 1595, when he devised a mechanical explanation for the tides requiring the Earth's motions. He first openly expressed this preference in a letter in 1597, but kept it private due to the danger posed by "foolish opponents". His invention of the "geometric and military compass" in 1597, a practical calculating device, shows his blend of theoretical and practical interests and became a source of income.
A personal blow and a valuable lesson came with the Capra plagiarism incident in 1606-1607. Another mathematician, Baldessar Capra, published a Latin version of Galileo's instrument treatise and implied Galileo stole the idea. Galileo successfully sued Capra, who was expelled. This experience, however, made Galileo more secretive about his discoveries and skeptical of others, and the accusation itself was later used by his enemies.
His continued work on motion led to important discoveries around 1607-1608, including the relationship between speed and distance in falling bodies and the parabolic path of projectiles. He was working on a book on this when the invention of the telescope changed everything.
**The Telescope: Opening Eyes and Stirring Troubles**
News of a device that made distant objects appear closer reached Venice and then Galileo in 1609. Recognizing its importance, especially for maritime Venice, Galileo quickly set about building his own. He rapidly improved it, creating instruments far more powerful than the initial models. Presenting one to the Venetian government earned him a significant salary increase and life tenure, though later misunderstandings about the terms made him seek employment elsewhere.
Using his improved telescope, Galileo made groundbreaking astronomical discoveries in late 1609 and early 1610. He saw mountains and craters on the moon, challenging the philosophical idea of perfect celestial spheres. He discovered four satellites orbiting Jupiter, contradicting the idea that Earth was the center of _all_ celestial motion. He also observed previously unseen stars and realized the Milky Way was made of countless stars.
These discoveries, published in his 1610 book _Starry Messenger_, caused a sensation among the public but were met with ridicule and accusations of fraud from many philosophers and astronomers who dismissed them as optical illusions. Some, like the philosophers Cremonini and Libri, simply refused to look through the instrument. Kepler, however, accepted the discoveries and confirmed them himself.
The demand from critics for a complete theory of optics before trusting telescopic observations highlights a key point for Drake: it shows science lacks philosophical justification, a truth for modern science just as for Galileo's. Critics wanting certainty over observation were essentially prioritizing philosophy over empirical evidence. Galileo, while lacking a full theory, meticulously described simple experiments with mirrors that supported his interpretation of what he saw on the moon, even measuring lunar mountains. Yet, opponents wouldn't concede the slightest irregularity.
He continued his astronomical work, discovering the phases of Venus (evidence against the Ptolemaic system). He visited Rome in 1611, where he was well-received by Jesuit astronomers and even met the Pope. There was no sign yet of theological opposition.
**The Growing Storm: Philosophy, the Bible, and the Church**
The conflict began to escalate not primarily with astronomers or theologians, but with philosophers. A debate about floating bodies in 1611, stemming from fundamental Aristotelian concepts of condensation and rarefaction, brought Galileo into direct conflict with university professors who saw his approach as a threat. Galileo's experimental demonstrations and a resulting treatise on floating bodies proved highly popular but drew strong attacks from philosophers who felt their entire logical system was threatened if even minor principles were questioned. This highlights how deeply entrenched Aristotelian natural philosophy was in the academic world.
A more serious front opened when philosophers, realizing reason was against them, began appealing to the Bible to support their arguments against Galileo. Galileo saw this as an "impious action" and a betrayal of their own principles. He believed philosophy professors were the real instigators behind priests speaking out against him.
This brings us to the events of 1613-1616. Galileo argued that purely scientific matters should be decided by "sensate experiences and necessary demonstrations," separate from matters of faith. He drew upon the precedent of early Church Fathers, like St. Augustine, who advised against linking Christian faith to irrelevant worldly knowledge like astronomy, especially if it required distracting study or risked discrediting faith if scientific understanding changed. Galileo strongly urged the Church _against_ intervening in scientific debates, not because he questioned their right, but because he sincerely believed it would harm the Church's credibility in the long run.
The incident at Christina's breakfast, where a professor raised the biblical miracle of Joshua stopping the sun to challenge the Copernican system, triggered Galileo's detailed Letter to Castelli (later expanded into the Letter to Christina) on the relationship between science and Scripture. He argued that the Bible used language accessible to ordinary people and should not be interpreted literally in scientific matters, especially since it could lead to contradictions even within the accepted cosmology. He felt secure in this position based on Church tradition.
Things heated up when Thomas Caccini, a young Dominican possibly seeking career advancement, denounced Galileo and "Galileists" from the pulpit, using the Joshua miracle as his text. This sermon caused a stir. Niccolò Lorini, another Dominican, copied Galileo's Letter to Castelli and sent it to the Roman Inquisition for investigation, though initially without accusations. The Inquisition reviewed the letter and found it "theologically unexceptional," suggesting they weren't actively seeking a reason to censure Galileo based on scientific views at this point; the issue was more driven by his personal enemies and an ambitious priest.
Cardinal Bellarmine, a key figure, advised Galileo that the Copernican view couldn't be "held or defended" as truth because it contradicted Scripture, but could be used "hypothetically". Many scholars think Galileo should have accepted this. Drake argues Galileo's refusal wasn't necessarily Copernican zeal, but his conviction that the Church shouldn't take an official stance on a scientific matter at all. He believed making such propositions matters of faith risked future condemnation if science later proved the Earth moved.
**The 1616 Injunction: The Crucial Misunderstanding**
The recommendations of the theological qualifiers in early 1616 declared the propositions that the sun is the center and the earth moves to be "foolish and absurd in Philosophy, and formally heretical inasmuch as it contradicts the express opinion of Holy Scriptures in many places".
Based on this, Pope Paul V instructed Bellarmine to tell Galileo he could no longer "hold or defend" these propositions. If Galileo resisted, the Commissary General of the Inquisition was authorized to issue a more stringent personal order, forbidding him to "hold, defend, or teach" the propositions "in any way, orally or in writing". The nuance here is critical: a general instruction for all Catholics (not to hold/defend as truth) vs. a personal, stricter command specifically to Galileo (not even to discuss or teach).
What _exactly_ happened at the meeting on February 26, 1616, became the central point of contention years later. There are two conflicting documents: an unsigned notary's memorandum stating Galileo was immediately given the strict "hold, defend, or teach" command by the Commissary, and an affidavit from Bellarmine saying Galileo was only told of the general censure and that he must no longer "hold or defend" the propositions. Drake considers both genuine.
Drake's hypothesis, based partly on a later statement by Galileo, suggests the Commissary arrived uninvited at Bellarmine's residence and issued the stricter "teach" command unauthorized, after Bellarmine had already quietly informed Galileo not to object. Bellarmine then privately reprimanded the Commissary and likely instructed Galileo to disregard the stricter command and rely on the cardinal's affidavit, which omitted the word "teach".
Following this, a decree was issued placing books treating the Earth's motion as real or reconciling it with the Bible on the Index of Prohibited Books, subject to correction. Bellarmine assured Galileo he was safe as long as he obeyed the command not to hold or defend Copernicanism as truth. Galileo, feeling effectively silenced on Copernicanism as truth, turned to other scientific work.
**The Road to the Dialogue and the Final Trial**
After 1616, Galileo worked on developing his longitude scheme using Jupiter's satellites and returned to his treatise on motion. However, he was drawn into a new controversy over comets (1618), criticizing the views of Jesuit astronomers like Orazio Grassi (writing as Sarsi). This led to Galileo's famous book _The Assayer_ (1623), which, while ostensibly about comets, was a powerful statement on the nature of scientific reasoning, contrasting it with the "logical quibbles" of natural philosophers. It's here he states philosophy "is written in this grand book the universe," written in the language of mathematics.
The publication of _The Assayer_ coincided with Maffeo Barberini, an admirer of Galileo, becoming Pope Urban VIII. Galileo visited Rome in 1624 and had several audiences with the new Pope, who seemed regretful of the 1616 edict. Galileo believed he obtained permission to publish his tide theory, provided he treated the Earth's motions only hypothetically and didn't claim they could be proved by earthly experiments or celestial observations. This understanding seemed to allow him to publish his ideas without directly violating the 1616 ruling, as he understood it (based on Bellarmine's affidavit).
Based on this understanding, Galileo began writing his _Dialogue Concerning the Two Chief Systems of the World—Ptolemaic and Copernican_. Written in dialogue form, featuring spokesmen for the Aristotelian/Ptolemaic view, the Copernican view (Galileo's voice), and an interested layman, it aimed to educate the public and subtly advocate for the Earth's motion to explain his tide theory. He structured it as conversations over four "days".
Obtaining a license for the book was difficult, and delays in publication and distribution meant copies didn't reach Rome immediately after its appearance in Florence in March 1632. Then, suddenly, in August 1632, an order came from the Roman Inquisition to stop sales, and Galileo was summoned to Rome for trial.
What caused this sudden reversal? Drake argues that Pope Urban VIII had been shown the unsigned notary's memorandum from 1616, which included the strict "nor teach" command. Since Galileo had never mentioned receiving such a personal injunction (because, according to Drake's hypothesis, Bellarmine had told him to ignore it and rely on the affidavit), it appeared to Urban VIII that Galileo had deliberately disobeyed a direct legal order by publishing the _Dialogue_, which certainly discussed and implicitly taught the Copernican view. Drake suggests Scheiner, Galileo's Jesuit adversary from the sunspot controversy, was likely responsible for unearthing and presenting this document.
Despite ill health and age, Galileo was compelled to travel to Rome in early 1633. At the trial, which began in April 1633, the main issue was the 1616 meeting. Galileo presented Bellarmine's affidavit, which only mentioned the command not to "hold or defend". The prosecutor read the notary's memorandum with the "teach" clause. Galileo maintained he only recalled Bellarmine's admonition and relied on the affidavit. Crucially, the Inquisition found no signed document to support the notary's memorandum.
Although Galileo had won the specific legal point regarding the existence of the strict command, the Inquisition couldn't acquit him without damaging its own authority. A private arrangement was made for Galileo to admit some minor fault (he attributed it to vanity in arguments) in exchange for leniency. However, he was condemned for "vehement suspicion of heresy" and sentenced to indefinite imprisonment. Drake notes that no scientific question was actually debated or decided at the trial; the charge was solely about disobedience to an order.
**The Final Years: Under Surveillance, Still Creating**
Galileo's sentence was commuted to custody, first with the understanding and humane Archbishop Piccolomini in Siena, which Drake says likely saved his life and sanity. The Archbishop encouraged him to resume work on his long-planned treatise on motion.
In late 1633, Galileo was permitted to return to his villa at Arcetri, near Florence, where he spent the rest of his life under surveillance by Inquisition officers. His beloved eldest daughter, Sister Maria Celeste, a nun in a nearby convent, died shortly after in April 1634, a blow from which he took a long time to recover.
Despite being silenced by the Church, Galileo's work continued to circulate and be published abroad, often in Latin translations that reached a wider European audience. His _Mechanics_ was translated into French, and the suppressed _Dialogue_ appeared in Latin. His _Letter to Christina_, arguing against mixing Scripture and science, was also printed. Drake notes that the Jesuits attempted to prevent publication of his works wherever possible, enforcing the Roman ruling.
Galileo's final masterpiece, _Two New Sciences_, was completed during these years and published in Leiden in 1638 by the Elzevirs. Written in dialogue form like the _Dialogue_, it systematically covered fundamental areas of physics: the structure and resistance of materials and the laws of motion (acceleration, projectile paths). Drake notes that despite the dramatic stories, the surveillance by Inquisition officers at Arcetri was not harsh; they often became fond of Galileo and mainly just monitored his visitors and reported them.
By the time _Two New Sciences_ was printed, Galileo was totally blind, a cruel blow for a man whose observational talent was so crucial to his discoveries. He famously lamented his loss of sight, which shrunk the universe he had so vastly expanded through his work. His young pupil, Vincenzio Viviani, came to live with him, serving as amanuensis and later writing a valuable (though sometimes inaccurate) biography based on their time together.
In his last years, Galileo still engaged in intellectual debate, notably corresponding with Fortunio Liceti, a philosopher who attacked his views. Though Galileo showed a somewhat more conciliatory tone towards Aristotle himself, he patiently refuted Liceti's misrepresentations and errors, illustrating the continued resistance of academic philosophers to his empirical, mathematical approach.
Drake highlights Galileo's ability to use homely examples and literary skill, learned partly from poets, to keep readers focused on observable reality rather than abstract philosophical "worlds on paper". He saw this literary approach as a tool to make science accessible to laymen, just as he used mathematics for his colleagues.
Galileo died at Arcetri on January 9, 1642. Despite his condemnation, many contemporaries, even some close to the Church hierarchy, recognized his immense intellect and significance.
**Wrapping Up: Galileo's Legacy as Seen Here**
Drake concludes that Galileo felt crushed by the verdict of "vehement suspicion of heresy" because it cut him off from the Church he loved, because he knew he was innocent of heresy, and because it condemned his life's work. However, he never questioned his faith. He didn't see Copernicanism as absolute truth, but rather saw the Ptolemaic/Aristotelian systems as demonstrably more flawed based on evidence.
For Galileo, science wasn't about reaching final, complete truth, but was a "method of successive approximations," an unending search where one can be confident of getting closer each year. He blamed the outcome not on theologians in general, but on the "frauds and stratagems" employed by philosophy professors who had misled the authorities. His real "uprightness of intentions," in Drake's view, was his campaign for freedom of scientific inquiry from Church intervention, not support for Copernicus.
Drake argues that the Church suffered for turning its back on Galileo, while Galileo's profound intellect would serve as a guide for "all posterity" in the search for truth.
**Further Ideas and Questions to Explore:**
Reading about Galileo through this lens might spark some thoughts:
- **The Role of Personality:** How much did Galileo's personality – his pugnaciousness combined with apparent prudence and deeply held beliefs – truly influence the events of his life and his conflict with authority?
- **Sincerity vs. Strategy:** Drake makes a strong case for Galileo's sincere religious zeal. How does this perspective change our understanding of his actions and writings compared to viewing him solely as a defender of scientific truth?
- **The Nature of Evidence:** The conflict highlights different ideas of what constitutes "incontrovertible evidence" (Bellarmine's requirement) versus "preponderance of evidence" (Galileo's scientific approach). How do these different views on evidence shape understanding and conflict?
- **Science and Philosophy:** Galileo sought to free science from philosophy's guidance while believing a better philosophy might emerge later. How does his vision of their relationship compare to modern views?
- **The 1616 Meeting:** The conflicting documents and Drake's hypothesis about the 1616 injunction are central to the trial. How significant is this historical mystery to the overall story of Galileo's condemnation?
- **Communication and Authority:** Galileo's attempts to argue with philosophers and theologians, and his eventual condemnation, show the challenges of communicating across different domains of knowledge and authority. What lessons can be drawn from this about intellectual and institutional conflict?